by John Hansen
1825. William Blake. Job Plate 11. |
One of the perennial questions in philosophy is that, if God is both all-powerful and all-loving—assuming, that is, that he* exists—how is it that he permits suffering and evil in this world? We may imagine, for example, the gruesome suffering of a child, or a natural catastrophe.
One of the most influential thinkers in this area was John Hick (1922-2012), an American philosopher of religion and a theologian. Hick was an unconventional thinker, to the extent that he was twice the subject of heresy hearings. Yet his arguments on human suffering set the agenda. Hick held, to put it simply, that there is no evil in our suffering, but suffering improves our souls. That is, suffering is ultimately good, and merely appears to be evil.
There are multiple biblical references that suggest Hick's thesis: not only does God permit human suffering, but he actually endorses it. The story of Job is the prototype where God actually allows Satan to harm the righteous person (Job) in order to make him more ‘god-like’.
Since Hick, there have been new arguments, which Hick himself could hardly have imagined. Lately, there has been great interest in B.C. Johnson, who is not a theologian—yet through the strength of his arguments, has gained a large following. Johnson holds, to put it too simply, that everywhere, awful ‘accidents’ happen without the interventions of an all-powerful God. Therefore God is evil, or part good and part evil.
However, we find many unexamined assumptions, in both Hick and Johnson. We here examine some of them.
1. Both Hick and Johnson assume that God is personal—essentially, human in nature. Yet nowhere do they discuss this assumption. Is God human? If so, how? Thus they assign to God human codes of conduct. As a result, their discussion about God is essentially one about human morality. The question arises: do we justifiably refer to human morality, expecting God to conform with what is ‘human’?
2. Johnson assumes that God 'has refused to help' us in our sufferings -- and thus he must be evil. The assumption is that God would help us, unasked. One could conceive of an all-powerful, all-loving God who would not intervene in human affairs unless he was petitioned to do so—through a person with the requisite ‘faith’ to make the request. It would not be illogical to assume that God should be asked, by someone who believed that it was worth asking.
3. Almost every example that Johnson uses to question the goodness of God is found in his use of ‘accidents’. The assumption here, however, is that God has power over that realm. Even an all-powerful God could, presumably, leave some things alone. One could posit that a good God would not want to disturb the accidents of nature, because such intervention could disturb the flow of our environmental process. Perhaps he chooses rather to be all-powerful in the spiritual realm.
4. Hick, on the other hand, asks whether accidents can ever be called evil. In that case, can one assume a motive? A classic example is a hornet’s sting. Was there evil intent? Hick equates moral evil with human wickedness, and non-moral evil as equivalent to human pain and suffering from other sources. The distinction is important because Hick suggests that, in the case of human wickedness, we as free agents are in control. God himself may have no evil intent.
5. Johnson questions the theist’s ‘retreat to faith’ to explain God’s goodness. Such faith, he holds, cannot be justified in a wider context. When one casts an eye over history, God’s record is not good. Yet may it not be a category mistake? Faith is a matter of spiritual ascertainment and may make little sense when applied to human rules or philosophical analysis. Faith may not need to be ‘justifiable’ in terms of our own notions of right and wrong.
6. Skeptics may assume that God should have created the world as a hedonistic paradise devoid of human suffering. Suffering and evil may themselves be interpreted as good. God may have created the world to include pain and suffering. The necessity of such suffering, in turn, would bring about God-like characteristics that are necessary. According to Hick, if God were to eradicate all human suffering, we would drift through life aimlessly as if in a dream.
7. A final assumption of the skeptic is that God knows nothing of suffering. Yet an omnipotent, good God himself may have suffered throughout history, just as much as humanity has done, if not more. Such an all-powerful God may believe that it is necessary for human beings to suffer in a similar way as he has done, in order to become more like him, in a different state of existence.
Whether or not one agrees with Hick’s conclusions, it is submitted that his arguments are more plausible than Johnson’s, in that they do not attempt to analyse an unanalysable faith. We may have no better language to talk about it than this.
* I follow Rabbi Aryeh Kaplan: ‘We refer to G-d using masculine terms simply for convenience's sake ...’
Thank you, John.
ReplyDeleteSuffering--or rather, the nature of suffering--has a lot to do with hope and despair. Meaningful suffering brings hope. Meaningless suffering brings despair.
In North America in particular, there are two great theological streams--that suffering is ultimately good a) for the future of the world or b) for the future of the individual. Personally, I do not see how hope can exist unless it is personal.
You write, 'not only does God permit human suffering, but he actually endorses it'. This seems to represent option b). However, that may not be the necessary corollary. I wonder whether the view here described, that God 'actually endorses suffering', assumes a personal hope.
A fascinating discussion, John.
ReplyDelete“The question arises: do we justifiably refer to human morality, expecting God to conform with what is ‘human’?” The short answer, to my mind, is ‘No’. I suspect that our knee-jerk bias toward anthropomorphism gets us nowhere in understanding a god, should there be one. Any god is likely an abstraction, at least to the extent of having unknowable form.
I’ve always believed that ‘expecting God to conform with what is human’ shortchanges those qualities a god might actually have. Bias skews our vision of a god’s features. Surely a god would vastly differ — at minimum, be ‘greater’ — in all discernible and undiscernible respects.
By extension, I suspect that unknowability extends to trying to understand the category of ‘evil’. That is, to understand evil beyond just a handy, albeit terribly unimaginative construct designed only to serve our need to compartmentalize human behaviour and natural events. A placeholder, if you will, given we know no better.
It seems there are a six (or 500) basic questions (that may uncover assumptions) to any discussion of this nature. Firstly, does God exist. If yes, then is this God knowable? And if God is knowable, is He altogether knowable, or are there aspects of his 'Godness' that are unknowable? If God is knowable either fully or in part, in what way is this knowledge attained, and then, who gets to decide what the right answer to those questions are, and then finally, who gets to decide who gets to decide what the final answers to those questions are. The Theodicy question assumes there is a God, that He is good and that He IS personal- and intimately involved. I was never clear about who got to decide who decided that that was true - but when he said it I believe he was raising his voice and waving his arms - so I believed him. I do believe that God is intimately personal, and perfectly loving - and His NOT getting involved is simply an expression of His perfect love.
ReplyDelete